Значение слова "AVERROËS" найдено в 3 источниках

AVERROËS

найдено в "Encyclopedia of medieval literature"
Averroës: translation

(Ibn Rushd)
(1126–1198)
   The most important Muslim Aristotelian philosopher and the most renowned scholar of Islamic Spain was Ibn Rushd, known in the West as Averroës the Commentator for his influential commentaries on Aristotle. Averroës was a jurist, a physician, an astronomer, and a prolific writer whose commentaries, through translations into Hebrew and Latin composed by Andalusian Jews, exerted an influence on medieval Jewish philosophy and Latin scholasticism even greater than he had on Muslim philosophy.
   Averroës was born in Córdoba in 1126 to a family of learned jurists. Details of his early education are unknown, but he clearly had excellent training in law, grammar, literature, medicine, and theology in his early years. He is known to have been in Marrakesh in 1153, and seems to have met ‘Abd al-Mu’min, the first Almohad ruler of Spain. He returned to Marrakesh in 1163 and became acquainted with the court vizier and physician Ibn Tufayl, who introduced Averroës to the new Almohad ruler, Abū Ya’qūb Yūsuf, whose interest in philosophy led him to ask Averroës to compose Arabic commentaries on some of Aristotle’s more obscure works. Averroës’s first commentary appeared in 1169, the same year he was appointed to a judgeship in Seville.
   In 1171 Averroës returned to Córdoba, where according to some sources he became chief judge. Then in 1182, upon the retirement of his old sponsor Ibn Tufayl, Averroës became court physician, a position he kept after Abū Ya’qūb Yūsuf was succeeded by his son Abū Yūsuf Ya’qūb in 1184. But in 1195, for reasons that remain obscure, Averroës was disgraced and exiled to Lucenna (near Córdoba). It seems likely that the dismissal from court was prompted by conservative religious authorities’ objections to some of his philosophical arguments, since all of his philosophical and theological texts were burnt in conjunction with his exile.At some point, however, Averroës was pardoned and allowed to return to Marrakesh, where he lived in retirement until his death in 1198.
   Averroës wrote 38 commentaries on Aristotle, of which 28 are extant in Arabic, 36 in Hebrew, and 34 in Latin. He considered it his primary task to correct the erroneous interpretations of Aristotle made by earlier philosophers, in particular the 10th-century eastern Muslim philosopher Avicenna. The commentaries—on such texts as Aristotle’s Physics, Metaphysics, Rhetoric, Poetics, De anima, and others—are of three types: major (which contain the text as well as commentary), middle (an extensive interpretive essay), and epitome (a shorter interpretation). For some Aristotelian texts, he wrote all three types of commentary. In addition Averroës wrote commentaries on Plato’s Republic, Porphyry’s Isagoge, Ptolemy’s Almagest, and other classical Greek texts. In addition, he wrote influential works on Islamic law (Bidāyat al-mujtahid) and on medicine (al-Kulliyyāt).He also wrote works defending the study of philosophy against those who considered it incompatible with strict Islamic law. His best-known work in this vein is the Tahāfut al-Tahāfut (The Incoherence of the Incoherence), a direct response to the Muslim attack on Aristotelianism (The Incoherence of the Philosophers) by the Persian scholar AL-GAZāLI (d. 1111).
   Averroës’s influence on medieval and Renaissance European thought cannot be overstated. Through his commentaries, the texts and interpretations of Aristotle’s works made available in Europe stimulated philosophers in the Latin West and in Judaism. Some of the doctrines with which he became associated in the West were the idea of the eternity of the world, the denial of individual providence, and most important (following from his discussion of divine and human intellect), the denial of individual immortality. All of these doctrines were condemned by orthodox Christian theologians. Latin “Averroists,” however, developed what became known as the doctrine of the double truth, by which they claimed that philosophy and theology could reach truths that are mutually contradictory. Averroës himself never made such a claim—he argued that his views were compatible with Islamic faith—but the doctrine of the doubletruth seems to have become popular at the University of Paris in the 13th century.
   Bibliography
   ■ Averroës. Tahafut al-Tahafut (The Incoherence of the Incoherence). Translated by Simon van den Bergh. 2 vols. London: Luzac, 1954.
   ■ Butterworth, Charles E., ed. and trans. Averroes’Middle Commentaries on Aristotle’s Categories and De interpretatione. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1983.
   ■ ———, ed. and trans. Averroës’ Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle’sTopics,” “Rhetoric,” andPoetics.” Albany: State University of New York Press, 1977.
   ■ Davidson,Herbert A. Alfarabi, Avicenna, and Averroes on Intellect: Their Cosmologies, Theories of the Active Intellect, and Theories of Human Intellect. New York: Oxford University Press, 1992.
   ■ Hyman, Arthur, and James J.Walsh. Philosophy in the Middle Ages: The Christian, Islamic, and Jewish Traditions. 2nd ed. Indianapolis, Ind.: Hackett, 1983.
   ■ Leaman, Oliver. Averroes and His Philosophy. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1988.
   ■ Rosenthal, E. I. J., ed. and trans. Averroës’ Commentary on Plato’s Republic. Reprint with corrections. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1969.


найдено в "Philosophy dictionary"
Averroës: translation

(or Ibn Rushd ) (1126–1198)
The most distinguished and influential Islamic Aristotelian, Averroës was born in 1126 in Cordoba, and was educated in law and various sciences. He lived partly in Marrakesh, and became a judge in Seville in 1169. Towards the end of his life he fell into disgrace, but although exiled for a short time was restored to favour, and died in Marrakesh. The majority of his works were commentaries on the writings of Aristotle. Averroës wrote with the intention of rescuing Aristotle from Neoplatonic and religious impurities, especially as found in the works of Avicenna . In particular, whereas for Avicenna existence is an accident of essence, or in other words the universal or form precedes the individual thing, for Averroës individual substances are the primary existents, and the distinction between them and their essence is the work of the mind.He also criticized Avicenna's cosmological argument, holding instead that only physical arguments, such as that showing the need for a prime mover, can prove the existence of physical things. Averroës was much concerned with improving and expanding upon Aristotle's doctrine of the intellect and the soul, holding a curious doctrine of a universal and immaterial passive intellect, common to all, and providing what is common, and immortal, in human beings. Because he held non-Christian doctrines, including the eternity of the world, the absence of individual providence, and the doctrine of merely collective immortality, Averroës became associated with the doctrine of double truth, the slightly underhand way of reconciling theology and philosophy, although he himself never subscribed to such a view. As well as his 38 commentaries on Aristotle, he wrote the Incoherence of the Incoherence against the anti-rationalism of Al-Ghazali, works on medicine, a commentary on Plato's Republic, and treatises on religion.


найдено в "Scientists"
Averroës: translation

Averroës (or Abu Al-Walid Muhammad Ibn Ahmad Ibn Rushd )
(1126–1198) Spanish–Muslim physician and philosopher
Averroës, also known simply as ‘The Commentator’ to the Latin West, or Ibn Rushd, came from a family of jurists and was born in Cordoba in Moorish Spain. He himself trained in law and medicine and later served as qadi or judge in Seville and Cordoba. In 1182 he was appointed physician to the court of caliph Abu Ya`qub Yusuf in Marrakesh and to his son, Abu Yusuf Ya`qub, in 1195 but was recalled shortly before his death.
In the field of medicine Averroës produced his Kulliyat fi al tib(General Medicine) between 1162 and 1169. He is however better known for his great commentaries on Aristotle but, above all, for his Tahafut al-Tahafut (The Incoherence of the Incoherence), a strong attack on the Muslim philosopher al-Ghazzali's Tahafut al-Falasifah (The Incoherence of the Philosophers). The work was more influential in the Latin Christian West than in the Muslim East, and its contents paved the way for the medieval separation of faith and reason.


T: 130